Cecilia
Heyes' paper “New
Thinking: the evolution of human cognition”
has just been published in Philosophical Transactions of the Royal
Society and is available online.
It is the introductory paper to a special
issue where the
other papers are behind a pay wall.
It
is over 20 years since I abandoned my research on CODIL
and took early retirement,effectively on health grounds, and
just over a year since I decided to come online to see what relevant
developments had happened during the intervening years. While my
research was oriented to providing a flexible information tool to
help people handle poorly structured problems many aspects of the
design involved trying to understand how people processed
information. As such I was thrilled to discover Cecilia's review as a
means of getting back up to speed.
Her dismissal of the
approach which she refers to as “Evolutionary Psychology” reminds
me very much of some of the disagreements I had with the “Artificial
Intelligentsia” in the 1970s and 80s. Then the establishment view
(and unfortunately the establishment effectively controlled the
research purse strings) was that the way forward to understanding
intelligence was to study mathematically well defined tasks such as
playing chess and solving formal logical problems of little practical
relevance to the rather messy real world we actually live in. It is
clear from the review that many cognitive psychologists have been
following the stored program computer philosophy of trying to build
specific models for specific tasks. I was therefore delighted that
this approach is being rejected. The idea that the brain consists of
general purpose units which can do anything fits in well with what I
was trying to say some thirty years ago – when I was suggesting
that the starting point for modelling the way humans process
information should be the flexible way they could handle open end,
fuzzy and otherwise ill-defined problems, and not detailed studies of
well-defined tasks.
Following on from a
discussion of brain structures I came to an interesting section which
covers recent studies on human evolution and the behaviour of animal.
I felt things were going in the right direction when I read:
Whiten
& Erdal's
pre-Pleistocene perspective focuses on the comparison of humans with
chimpanzees. They identify five major components of the 'human
socio-cognitive niche', five dimensions on which humans excel -
cooperation, egalitarianism, theory of mind, language and culture -
and in each case they review evidence that the behaviour/cognitive
competence was present to some degree in the common ancestor of
humans and chimpanzees. For example, chimpanzees cooperate when
hunting and mounting raiding parties on other troops; show signs of
egalitarianism when sharing meat and forming coalitions that thwart
dominant males; appear to be able to attribute perceptions and goals,
if not beliefs and desires, to others; and, in addition to having an
extensive repertoire of communicative gestures, chimpanzees use
vocalizations in a flexible, context-dependent way to signal
information about food and social roles. Whiten &
Erdal note that there is a 'yawning gulf in the cultural
achievements of chimpanzees and humans', but even in this domain they
find signs of continuity. Field studies have yielded reports of more
than 40 chimpanzee traditions-involving food processing, tool use and
various social behaviours - and many of the social learning
processes found in humans are also present in other animals,
including chimpanzees.
My
approach to thinking about biological evolution is to assume that
there is nothing new under the sun, as everything is no more than a
slight increment on what has gone before, and that human thinking
mechanisms were little more than greatly amplified versions of the
mechanisms of our ape relatives, For the same reason I was pleased to
see that in the abstract of Cecilia's paper Grist
and Mills: on the cultural origins of cultural learning
she writes:
I find that recent empirical work in comparative psychology,
developmental psychology and cognitive neuroscience provides
surprisingly little evidence of genetic adaptation, and ample
evidence of cultural adaptation.
However
as I went further into the main paper I found that while there was a
lot of very interesting science I felt that often the wrong questions
were being asked. This is typified by the words from the start of
the the section headed What? Domain-general Developmental
Mechanisms:
Many
articles in this theme issue ... present a very different view. They
suggest that humans are born with extraordinarily powerful
cognative-developmental mechanisms. ... The genetically inherited
cognitive-developmental mechanisms use computational processes that
are also present in other animals, but they are uniquely powerful in
their range, capacity and flexibility.
I
cannot possibly agree with such a view. Of course there are
exceptional aspects of human behaviour – but to suggest that we are
born with extraordinarily powerful and unique
mechanisms run counter to the way biological evolution works.
Nearly all changes are made in small increments – and these changes
are often related to comparative rates of development of various
parts of the body rather than fundamental changes in plan. The real
problem in the above statement is that there seems to be no clear
model of how the brain processes information at the general cognitive
level and as humans are not impartial observers it is very attractive
to think that the “missing links” in the brain model are
“extraordinarily powerful and unique mechanisms”.
I discussed the fact that
there were missing links in brain research a year ago today in the
opening brainstorm The
Black Hole in Brain Research,
If you try and stand back from the detailed research and get an
overview of brain research the situation is rather as if some aliens
had obtained a number of working personal computers – each running
different applications. One machine is dissected to try and
understand the wiring, and monitors are installed in others to see
which circuits are electrically active as the applications run. Other
alien scientists study individual application in great depeth – and
end up learning a lot about the applications – but gain virtually
no insight into how the tasks the computers are doing are related to
the hardware. In such circumstance it would be very easy for the
aliens to assume that the central processor of the computer contains
“extraordinarily
powerful and unique mechanisms”
when it is actually has a quite small set of operations which
manipulate numbers in a way which superficially appear to have little
to do with the tasks the computers are running. However we know that
the real power of the computer lies not in the hardware (different
computers can have different instruction sets) but in the way the
patterns of “0”s and “1”s in memory are linked together.
Superficially there can't be anything much simpler that an array of
binary digits – which is why the aliens failed to understand the
role of software.
So
back to the brain and the evolution of human cognition. If you are
talking about any form of evolutionary model you need to have a clear
starting point and a clear finishing point so that you can assess
what has changed, and consider the evolutionary pressures that
brought about that change. This is easy enough with an organ like the
hand, where one can examine both living and fossil examples.
To
properly understand the evolution of human cognition you also need to
have an understanding of the mechanisms within the brain (both animal
and human) so you can measure the evolutionary changes that have
taken place, and hopefully predict the likely reasons for the change.
Unfortunately it is effectively impossible to directly read out the
contents of a living brain of an animal to work out what it
understands, and there is no way we can ever get fossil brainwaves
from our long extinct forebears. But unless you have a clear idea of
the evolutionary starting point it is totally inappropriate to make
strong statements such as the finishing point includes
“extraordinarily
powerful and unique mechanisms”
especially in the light of the statement quoted earlier that there is
“surprisingly
little evidence of genetic adaptation”.
If
we cannot experimentally determine the starting point it could be
possible to look at models based on the minimal amount of information
an animal will need to remember past events and use the remembered
information to make simple predictions about the present. Given such
a model it should then be possible to ask how it would adapt to
various evolutionary pressures which lead towards what we know about
human cognition. If the process is successful we have a possible
evolutionary pathway and we can compare the start point and end point
mechanisms. If the approach is unsuccessful it should at least give
us clues as to how we might build a better starting model.
In
fact I have been exploring one possible model in this blog, for
instance in brainstorms such as An
Evolutionary Model of the Brains Internal Language
and Step
Outside the box to understand the Evolution of Intelligence.
I am well aware that the initial model has limitations, which is why
I welcome contributions to the “brainstorms”
on this blog, but the model appears to explain some features of in
human mental development over the last few million years, and
suggests a tripping point clear, where there could be a small but
significant change in the underlying mechanism. I will be preparing a
further brainstorm on this topic sometime in July, which will be
looking further than previous posts into the relationship between the
brain's biological mechanisms and cultural knowledge.
No comments:
Post a Comment